Jump to content

Material conditional

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Material conditional
IMPLY
Venn diagram of Material conditional
Definition
Truth table
Logic gate
Normal forms
Disjunctive
Conjunctive
Zhegalkin polynomial
Post's lattices
0-preservingno
1-preservingyes
Monotoneno
Affineno
Self-dualno

The material conditional (also known as material implication) is an operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol is interpreted as material implication, a formula is true unless is true and is false.

Material implication is used in all the basic systems of classical logic as well as some nonclassical logics. It is assumed as a model of correct conditional reasoning within mathematics and serves as the basis for commands in many programming languages. However, many logics replace material implication with other operators such as the strict conditional and the variably strict conditional. Due to the paradoxes of material implication and related problems, material implication is not generally considered a viable analysis of conditional sentences in natural language.

Notation

[edit]

In logic and related fields, the material conditional is customarily notated with an infix operator .[1] The material conditional is also notated using the infixes and .[2] In the prefixed Polish notation, conditionals are notated as . In a conditional formula , the subformula is referred to as the antecedent and is termed the consequent of the conditional. Conditional statements may be nested such that the antecedent or the consequent may themselves be conditional statements, as in the formula .

History

[edit]

In Arithmetices Principia: Nova Methodo Exposita (1889), Peano expressed the proposition "If , then " as Ɔ with the symbol Ɔ, which is the opposite of C.[3] He also expressed the proposition as Ɔ .[4][5][6] Hilbert expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as in 1918.[1] Russell followed Peano in his Principia Mathematica (1910–1913), in which he expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as . Following Russell, Gentzen expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as . Heyting expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as at first but later came to express it as with a right-pointing arrow. Bourbaki expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as in 1954.[7]

Definitions

[edit]

Semantics

[edit]

From a classical semantic perspective, material implication is the binary truth functional operator which returns "true" unless its first argument is true and its second argument is false. This semantics can be shown graphically in a truth table such as the one below. One can also consider the equivalence .

Truth table

[edit]

The truth table of :

FFT
FTT
TFF
TTT

The conditionals where the antecedent is false, are called "vacuous truths". Examples are ...

  • ... with false: "If Marie Curie is a sister of Galileo Galilei, then Galileo Galilei is a brother of Marie Curie."
  • ... with true: "If Marie Curie is a sister of Galileo Galilei, then Marie Curie has a sibling."

Syntactical properties

[edit]

The semantic definition by truth tables does not permit the examination of structurally identical propositional forms in various logical systems, where different properties may be demonstrated. The system considered here is Implicational (propositional) logic.

Implicational logic is a form of propositional logic where the only logical connective allowed is implication (). A symbol "" stands for false.

  • Minimal logic: By limiting the natural deduction rules of implicational logic to Implication Introduction (I) and Implication Elimination (E), one obtains minimal logic (as discussed by Johansson).[8] See below.
  • Intuitionistic logic: By adding Falsum Elimination (E) to these rules, one obtains intuitionistic logic. See below.
  • Classical logic: If Reductio ad Absurdum (RAA) is also permitted, the result is classical logic. See below.

The well-formed formulas of Implicational logic are:

  1. Each sentence-letter is a formula.
  2. "" is a formula.
  3. If and are formulae, so is .
  4. Nothing else is a formula.

The only primitive operation is "". All other logical operations, such as (negation), (conjunction) and (disjunction), are defined in terms of "":

Consider the following (candidate) natural deduction rules.

Implication Introduction (I)

If assuming one can derive , then one can conclude .

(I)

is an assumption that is discharged when applying the rule.

Implication Elimination (E)

This rule corresponds to modus ponens.

(E)


(E)

Reductio ad absurdum (RAA)

(RAA)

is an assumption that is discharged when applying the rule.

Falsum Elimination (E)

From falsum () one can derive any formula.
(ex falso quodlibet)

(E)

  • When only I and E are admitted as deduction rules, the system corresponds to minimal logic as defined by Johansson.[8]
  • When E is also admitted, the system defines intuitionistic logic.
E allows to prove , but not the reverse implication which would entail the law of excluded middle.
Proof of , using E
1.  [ p ]  // Assume
2.  [ p → ⊥ ]  // Assume
3.   // E (1, 2)
4.  (p → ⊥) → ⊥)  // I (2, 3), discharging 2
5.  p → ((p → ⊥) → ⊥)  // I (1, 4), discharging 1
  • When all four natural deduction rules are admitted, the system defines classical logic.
The extra RAA allows to prove .
Proof of , using RAA
1.  [ (p→⊥)→⊥ ]  // Assume
2.  [ p→⊥ ]  // Assume
3.   // E (1, 2)
4.  p  // RAA (2, 3), discharging 2
5.  ((p→⊥)→⊥) → p  // I (1, 4), discharging 1

A selection of theorems (classical logic)

[edit]

In classical logic material implication validates the following equivalences:

  • Contraposition:
  • Import-export:
  • Negated conditionals:
  • Or-and-if:
  • Commutativity of antecedents:
  • Left distributivity:

Similarly, on classical interpretations of the other connectives, material implication validates the following entailments:

  • Antecedent strengthening:
  • Vacuous conditional:
  • Transitivity:
  • Simplification of disjunctive antecedents:

Tautologies involving material implication include:

  • Reflexivity:
  • Totality:
  • Conditional excluded middle:

Discrepancies with natural language

[edit]

Material implication does not closely match the usage of conditional sentences in natural language. For example, even though material conditionals with false antecedents are vacuously true, the natural language statement "If 8 is odd, then 3 is prime" is typically judged false. Similarly, any material conditional with a true consequent is itself true, but speakers typically reject sentences such as "If I have a penny in my pocket, then Paris is in France". These classic problems have been called the paradoxes of material implication.[9] In addition to the paradoxes, a variety of other arguments have been given against a material implication analysis. For instance, counterfactual conditionals would all be vacuously true on such an account, when in fact some are false.[10]

In the mid-20th century, a number of researchers including H. P. Grice and Frank Jackson proposed that pragmatic principles could explain the discrepancies between natural language conditionals and the material conditional. On their accounts, conditionals denote material implication but end up conveying additional information when they interact with conversational norms such as Grice's maxims.[9][11]</ref> Recent work in formal semantics and philosophy of language has generally eschewed material implication as an analysis for natural-language conditionals.[11] In particular, such work has often rejected the assumption that natural-language conditionals are truth functional in the sense that the truth value of "If P, then Q" is determined solely by the truth values of P and Q.[9] Thus semantic analyses of conditionals typically propose alternative interpretations built on foundations such as modal logic, relevance logic, probability theory, and causal models.[11][9][12]

Similar discrepancies have been observed by psychologists studying conditional reasoning, for instance, by the notorious Wason selection task study, where less than 10% of participants reasoned according to the material conditional. Some researchers have interpreted this result as a failure of the participants to conform to normative laws of reasoning, while others interpret the participants as reasoning normatively according to nonclassical laws.[13][14][15]

See also

[edit]

Conditionals

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ a b Hilbert 1918.
  2. ^ Mendelson 2015.
  3. ^ Van Heijenoort 1967.
  4. ^ Note that the horseshoe symbol Ɔ has been flipped to become a subset symbol ⊂.
  5. ^ Nahas 2022, p. VI.
  6. ^ Allegranza 2015.
  7. ^ Bourbaki 1954, p. 14.
  8. ^ a b Johansson 1937.
  9. ^ a b c d Edgington 2008.
  10. ^ For example, "If Janis Joplin were alive today, she would drive a Mercedes-Benz", see Starr (2019)
  11. ^ a b c Gillies 2017.
  12. ^ Von Fintel 2011.
  13. ^ Oaksford & Chater 1994.
  14. ^ Stenning & Van Lambalgen 2004.
  15. ^ Von Sydow 2006.

Bibliography

[edit]
  • Allegranza, Mauro (2015-02-13). "elementary set theory – Is there any connection between the symbol ⊃ when it means implication and its meaning as superset?". Mathematics Stack Exchange. Stack Exchange Inc. Answer. Retrieved 2022-08-10.
  • Bourbaki, N. (1954). Théorie des ensembles. Paris: Hermann & Cie, Éditeurs. p. 14.
  • Edgington, Dorothy (2008). "Conditionals". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2008 ed.).
  • Van Heijenoort, Jean, ed. (1967). From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press. pp. 84–87. ISBN 0-674-32449-8.
  • Hilbert, D. (1918). Prinzipien der Mathematik (Lecture Notes edited by Bernays, P.).
  • Starr, Will (2019). "Counterfactuals". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]